A Level Religious Studies - Falsification Principle presents a challenge to religious language essay
“Antony Flew’s falsification principle presents a significant
challenge to religious language.”
Antony Flew’s falsification
principle stems from Karl Popper’s ideas which questions the meaningfulness of
religious statements by checking if they can be falsified. Flew applied this to
religious language, concluding it is nothing more than silly, meaningless
words. Whilst it could be argued Antony Flew’s falsification principle presents
a significant challenge to religious language, this essay will argue that it
does not.
It can be argued that Flew does
present a significant challenge to religious language because a religious
belief is changed to fit any circumstance. Flew says that this means the
statement is not meaningful and has no empirical implications. Flew uses his
own version of the Parable of the Gardener to explain this: two explorers find
a clearing in the jungle, one says a gardener must tend to it but the other
denies it. They wait but no gardener appears – but they try to detect them. One
says the gardener is invisible and undetectable. This shows how religious
believers do not allow for the falsification of their belief and turn to saying
that God is incomprehensible. Flew said that God ‘died a death of a thousand
qualification’, explaining that religious beliefs are continuously modified to
meet the challenges. Eventually, the beliefs fall far from the original claims
of God. Flew therefore does challenge religious language as he notes it lacks
meaning and has no empirical evidence.
However, Richard Swinburne says
that the falsification principle does not work for all statements, but they
still have meaning. He uses the analogy of the cupboard of toys to explain
this. It says that you cannot prove or falsify that the toys cannot leave the
cupboard when it is unsupervised, but the concept of their movement still has
enough meaning as it is something we can understand. This argument identifies a
fatal flaw in the principle Flew puts forward as it suggests that some
statements are meaningless just because they cannot be falsified. This
therefore suggests that Flew’s falsification principle does not provide a
significant challenge to religious language as it cannot be applied universally
and has to be done systematically to make his principle seem strong.
Flew’s falsification principle
can be argued to significantly challenge religious language because Ayer
agrees. A.J. Ayer even takes it a step further, denying the possibility of
God’s existence altogether on the grounds that there is no way of empirically
verifying his existence. He believed that ethical statements fell short of the
verification principle because they cannot be verified empirically. This
provides a significant challenge to the idea of religious language because it
concludes that it lacks any meaning or worth due to its lack of evidence. This
is a significant challenge because it is impossible to provide any solid,
empirical evidence in favour of God’s existence, meaning it is easy to take
Ayer’s conclusion at face value and say that religious language is meaningless.
R.M. Hare combats this, arguing
that religious language is meaningful because it is non-cognitive, and so
cannot have the falsification principle applied to it. Religious statements do
not make factual claims and so cannot be considered cognitive, thus making the
application of the falsification principle wrong. Hare says that religious
language is meaningful because they have great influence in believers’ lives, illustrating
some sense of meaning to that person. He also proposed that a believer’s
statements were ‘bliks’ – ways of regarding the world that may not based on
reason or fact and are neither falsifiable nor verifiable. This eliminates any
sense of challenge put forward by the falsification principle as it further reinforces
the idea that religious statements are unfalsifiable.
It can be argued that the
falsification principle does provide a significant challenge to religious
language. Karl Popper writes that “science is more concerned with falsification
of hypothesis than verification”, and so created the falsification principle as
the verification principle was deemed too flawed to be valid. He figured that a
scientific statement is one that is falsifiable, meaning that it would accept
evidence, if it existed to prove the statement false. This presents a
significant challenge to religious language as it highlights the need for
evidence which believers cannot offer; Popper and other philosopher consider
non-factual statements to be meaningless. As religious statements are not based
on fact and rather a belief, it makes sense for them to be called meaningless.
Despite this, Basil Mitchell puts
forward the argument that religious statements are meaningful even if they are
neither straightforwardly verifiable, nor falsifiable. Mitchell said that Flew
was wrong in his supposition that believers never allow anything to count
against their beliefs. He used the Parable of the Partisan and the Strange to
explore it. A Partisan meets a stranger who claims to be a resistance leader.
The stranger urges the Partisan to have faith in him, even if he is seen to be
acting against Partisan interests. The Partisan is committed to a belief in the
stranger’s integrity, but his friends think he is a fool to do so. The original
encounter with the stranger gives the Partisan sufficient confidence to hold
onto his faith in him even when there is evidence to the contrary. This is
important as it illustrates the concept of non-propositional faith, which is a
trust in God which may be held even when things suggest otherwise. Flew missed
this point, and Mitchell argues that believers do not allow anything to
conclusively falsify their belief in God, but this does not mean it is
meaningless. This knocks the falsification principle as it gives an explanation
as to why religious statements can be seem as meaningful despite being
attempted to be proven differently; the peculiar and problematic parts of
religious belief will be revealed at the end of time according to religious
belief.
In conclusion, the falsification
principle does manage to put forward some points about the meaningfulness of
religious language, but the arguments against Flew’s proposition set it back.
The falsification principle’s strengths rely on a number of factors which are
difficult to apply to religious language, and in some cases, have been proven
impossible to apply as the components are not present. It is important to
recognise that Flew’s confidence in empirical evidence as a final test of
meaning is also unfalsifiable. If he couldn’t think of circumstances where he
would say empirical evidence wasn’t necessary, him saying we need this evidence
is also empty. The falsification principle therefore falls apart, making it
very hard to say that it presents a significant challenge to religious
language.
Comments
Post a Comment